Results for 'Sellars on Proper Names'

1000+ found
Order:
  1. Keith Lehrer.Sellars on Proper Names - 1978 - In Joseph Pitt (ed.), The Philosophy of Wilfrid Sellars: Queries and Extensions. D. Reidel. pp. 217.
  2.  12
    Sellars on Proper Names and Belief Contexts.Keith Lehrer - 1978 - In Joseph Pitt (ed.), The Philosophy of Wilfrid Sellars: Queries and Extensions. D. Reidel. pp. 217--227.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  44
    51 years on: Searle on proper names revisited.Proper Names Revisited - 2010 - In Jan G. Michel, Dirk Franken & Attila Karakus (eds.), John R. Searle: Thinking About the Real World. Ontos. pp. 117.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  67
    Pomponazzi Contra Averroes on the Intellect.John Sellars - 2016 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 24 (1):45-66.
    This paper examines Pomponazzi's arguments against Averroes in his De Immortalitate Animae, focusing on the question whether thought is possible without a body. The first part of the paper will sketch the history of the problem, namely the interpretation of Aristotle's remarks about the intellect in De Anima 3.4-5, touching on Alexander, Themistius, and Averroes. The second part will focus on Pomponazzi's response to Averroes, including his use of arguments by Aquinas. It will conclude by suggesting that Pomponazzi's discussion stands (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  5. Jay F. Rosenberg.Linguistic Roles & Proper Names - 1978 - In Joseph Pitt (ed.), The Philosophy of Wilfrid Sellars: Queries and Extensions. D. Reidel. pp. 12--189.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6. In the space of reasons: selected essays of Wilfrid Sellars.Wilfrid Sellars - 2007 - Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. Edited by Kevin Scharp & Robert Brandom.
    Inference and meaning -- Some reflections on language games -- Language as thought and as communication -- Meaning as functional classification : a perspective on the relation of syntax to semantics -- Naming and saying -- Grammar and existence : a preface to ontology -- Abstract entities -- Being and being known -- The lever of Archimedes -- Some reflections on thoughts and things -- Mental events -- Phenomenalism -- The identity approach to the mind-body problem -- Philosophy and the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  7. Naming and saying.Wilfrid Sellars - 1962 - Philosophy of Science 29 (1):7-26.
    The essay adopts the Tractarian view that configurations of objects are expressed by configurations of names. Two alternatives are considered: The objects in atomic facts are (1) without exception particulars; (2) one or more particulars plus a universal (Gustav Bergmann). On (1) a mode of configuration is always an empirical relation: on (2) it is the logical nexus of 'exemplification.' It is argued that (1) is both Wittgenstein's view in the Tractatus and correct. It is also argued that exemplification (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  8. Is there a synthetic a priori?Wilfrid Sellars - 1953 - Philosophy of Science 20 (2):121-138.
    A survey of the literature on the problem of the synthetic a priori soon reveals that the term “analytic” is used in a narrower and a broader sense. In the narrower sense, a proposition is analytic if it is either a truth of logic or is logically true. By saying of a proposition that it is logically true, I mean, roughly, and with an eye on the problem of the relation of logical categories to natural languages, that when defined terms (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  9.  69
    Pure pragmatics and epistemology.Wilfrid Sellars - 1947 - Philosophy of Science 14 (3):181-202.
    The attempt to draw a clear distinction between Philosophy and the empirical sciences can almost be taken as the defining trait of the analytic movement in contemporary philosophical thought. The empirical science that has most frequently threatened to swallow up questions of particular interest to philosophers since the time of Descartes has been psychology. Characteristic, then, of analytic philosophy has been the rejection of what it terms psychologism, that is to say, the mistake of identifying philosophical categories with those of (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  10.  72
    An ethics of the event.John Sellars - 2006 - Angelaki 11 (3):157 – 171.
    Deleuze, philosopher, son of Diogenes and Hypatia, sojourned at Lyon. Nothing is known of his life. He lived to be very old, even though he was often very ill. This illustrated what he himself had said: there are lives in which the difficulties verge on the prodigious. He defined as active any force that goes to the end of its power. This, he said, is the opposite of a law. Thus he lived, always going further than he had believed he (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  11.  71
    On the proper construal of the manifest-scientific image distinction: Brandom contra Sellars.Dionysis Christias - 2018 - Synthese 195 (3):1295-1320.
    In his new book, Brandom offers a new argument against the viability of Sellars’ scientific naturalism. Brandom attempts to show that if the Sellarsian it scientia mensura principle is understood as implying that manifest-image objects exist only if they are identical to scientific-image objects, it is undermined by the ‘Kant–Sellars’ thesis about identity which implies that manifest-image objects cannot be identical to scientific-image objects. This conclusion can be evaded by construing the relation between manifest and scientific objects as (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  12. The Lingua Franca of Nominalism: Sellars on Leibniz.Antonio Nunziante - 2018 - In Luca Corti & Antonio Nunziante (eds.), Sellars and the History of Modern Philosophy. New York, USA: Routledge. pp. 36-58.
    Leibniz can be counted among the remote, but still significant, sources of Sellars's philosophy. Such thesis, however, is meaningless unless its conceptual relevance is displayed. Therefore, it will be immediately added that Sellars's relation with Leibniz is focused on three main fundamental issues, which respectively concern (1) the concept of nature, (2) the concept of truth and (3) the concept itself of nominalism. Besides, there are other seemingly minor topics, which actually refers to the definition of abstract entities, (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13.  85
    The art of living : Stoic ideas concerning the nature and function of philosophy.John Sellars - 2001 - Dissertation, Warwick
    The aim of this thesis is to consider the relationship between philosophy and biography, and the bearing that this relationship has on debates concerning the nature and function of philosophy. There exists a certain tradition that conceives philosophy exclusively in terms of rational discourse and as such explicitly rejects the idea of any substantial relationship between philosophy and the way in which one lives. I shall argue that the claim that philosophy cannot have any impact upon biography is often based (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  21
    Geach on Proper Names.David Boersema - 2007 - The Proceedings of the Twenty-First World Congress of Philosophy 6:37-42.
    Recently, several philosophers of language have claimed that, at least in some respects, Peter Geach proposed a view about proper names that anticipated important features of the causal theory (or historical chain theory) that was later set forth by Saul Kripke and others. Quentin Smith, for example, in his essay, "Direct, Rigid Designation and A Posteriori Necessity: A History and Critique," says explicitly that "Geach (1969)... originated the causal or 'historical chain' theory of names" (1999). In his (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  99
    On proper names in belief ascriptions.Thomas McKay - 1981 - Philosophical Studies 39 (3):287-303.
  16.  67
    Kripke on proper names.Baruch A. Brody - 1979 - In A. French Peter, E. Uehling Theodore, Howard Jr & K. Wettstein (eds.), Contemporary Perspectives in the Philosophy of Language. University of Minnesota Press. pp. 64-69.
    Kripke has argued that proper names, as rigid designators, cannot be equivalent in meaning to definite descriptions. in this paper, i argue that definite descriptions are sometimes used rigidly and that proper names are equivalent to definite descriptions used rigidly.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  17.  10
    Kripke on proper names.Baruch A. Brody - 1977 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 2 (1):64-69.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  18.  92
    Geach on Proper Names.David Boersema - 2007 - The Proceedings of the Twenty-First World Congress of Philosophy 6:37-42.
    Recently, several philosophers of language have claimed that, at least in some respects, Peter Geach proposed a view about proper names that anticipated important features of the causal theory (or historical chain theory) that was later set forth by Saul Kripke and others. Quentin Smith, for example, in his essay, "Direct, Rigid Designation and A Posteriori Necessity: A History and Critique," says explicitly that "Geach (1969)... originated the causal or 'historical chain' theory of names" (1999). In his (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. Searle on proper names.Michael McKinsey - 1971 - Philosophical Review 80 (2):220-229.
    Searle has proposed a "presupposition-Theory" of proper names in which he maintains that names are not short for descriptions and which, He claims, Solves frege's puzzle as to how an identity-Sentence containing co-Referential names can be informative. Two possible interpretations of searle's view are proposed, And it is argued that neither interpretation can be used to solve frege's puzzle and that, On the most plausible interpretation of his view, Searle is committed to the thesis that (...) are short for descriptions after all. (shrink)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  40
    On Proper Names.Charles E. Jarrett - 1975 - Philosophy Research Archives 1:181-207.
    The main goal of this paper is to show that in Speech Acts, two of John Searle’s arguments fail to establish his thesis that proper names have sense, or descriptive content. It is argued, by considering counterexamples, that Searle’s test for the analyticity of statements is inadequate, that the argument from the "principle of identification" is therefore mistaken, and that, because of lack of attention to the distinction between meaning and sense, the argument from identity statements fails to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. Peirce on Proper Names and Individuation.Pierre Thibaud - 1987 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 23 (4):521-538.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  22.  31
    Aristotle on Proper Names.Eugene E. Ryan - 1981 - Apeiron 15 (1):38 - 47.
  23.  49
    On Proper Names And Frege’s Darstellungsweise.R. M. Martin - 1967 - The Monist 51 (1):1-8.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  4
    On Proper Names And Frege’s Darstellungsweise.R. M. Martin - 1967 - The Monist 51 (1):1-8.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  46
    Wittgenstein on proper names or: Under the circumstances.James Cappio - 1981 - Philosophical Studies 39 (1):87 - 105.
  26.  22
    Peirce on Proper Names.Francesco Bellucci - 2021 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 59 (3):483-510.
  27.  53
    Plantinga on proper names and propositions.Richard L. Mendelsohn - 1978 - Philosophical Studies 34 (2):211 - 218.
  28.  56
    In Defense of Donnellan on Proper Names.Antonio Capuano - 2020 - Erkenntnis 85 (6):1289-1312.
    Kripke’s picture of how people use names to refer to things has been the dominant view in contemporary philosophy of language. When it is mentioned at all, Donnellan’s view of proper names is considered the same as Kripke’s. It is certainly true that both Donnellan and Kripke rejected descriptivism about proper names and appealed to historical facts to determine whom a speaker is referring to by using a proper name. However, the relevant historical facts (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  29. Mill and Kripke on Proper Names and Natural Kind Terms.Stephen P. Schwartz - 2013 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 21 (5):925 - 945.
    Saul Kripke in his revolutionary and influential series of lectures from the early 1970s (later published as the book Naming and Necessity) famously resurrected John Stuart Mill's theory of proper names. Kripke at the same time rejected Mill's theory of general terms. According to Kripke, many natural kind terms do not fit Mill's account of general terms and are closer to proper names. Unfortunately, Kripke and his followers ignored key passages in Mill's A System of Logic (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  30.  96
    On the unification argument for the predicate view on proper names.Dolf Rami - 2014 - Synthese 191 (5):1-22.
    The predicate view on proper names opts for a uniform semantic representation of proper nouns like ‘Alfred’ as predicates on the level of logical form. Early defences of this view can be found in Sloat (Language, vol. 45, pp. 26–30, 1969) and Burge (J. Philos. 70: 425–439, 1973), but there is an increasing more recent interest in this view on proper names. My paper aims to provide a reconstruction and critique of Burge’s main argument for (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  31. Gareth Evans on Proper Names.Erhan Demircioglu - 2014 - Felsefe Tartismalari 50:1-9.
    The central aim of this paper is to argue against Evans’ hybrid theory of reference. I will show that Evans’ theory makes false predictions in the case of some thought-experiments. The paper has two sections. After providing a short presentation of Evans’ theory in the first section, I will move on to criticize it in the second section.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  17
    Barry Miller on proper names.Donald Nute - 1974 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 52 (3):237 – 239.
    This article is a comment on barry miller, "proper names and their distinctive senses," "australian journal of philosophy", Volume 52, Pages 201-210, January 1974. Miller claims that the sense of a name is its role of referring to the individual to which it has been attached in the act of naming. Miller also claims that names have unique senses and that it is impossible in principle to say what these senses are. Here it is shown that these (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  21
    Peirce and Russell on Proper Names.Helmut Pape - 1982 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 18 (4):339 - 348.
  34. Proper Names and Practices: On Reference without Referents.Mark Textor - 2010 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 81 (1):105-118.
    This is review essay of Mark Sainsbury's Reference without Referents. Its main part is a critical discussion of Sainsbury's proposal for the individuation of proper name using practices.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  35. Proper Names, Rigidity, and Empirical Studies on Judgments of Identity Across Transformations.Vilius Dranseika, Jonas Dagys & Renatas Berniūnas - 2020 - Topoi 39 (2):381-388.
    The question of transtemporal identity of objects in general and persons in particular is an important issue in both philosophy and psychology. While the focus of philosophers traditionally was on questions of the nature of identity relation and criteria that allow to settle ontological issues about identity, psychologists are mostly concerned with how people think about identity, and how they track identity of objects and people through time. In this article, we critically engage with widespread use of inferring folk judgments (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  36.  63
    Self, Language, and World: Problems from Kant, Sellars, and Rosenberg.James R. O'Shea & Eric M. Rubenstein (eds.) - 2010 - Ridgeview Publishing Co..
    Self, Language, and World: Problems from Kant, Sellars, and Rosenberg Edited by James R. O'Shea and Eric M. Rubenstein Introduction KANT Willem deVries, Kant, Rosenberg, and the Mirror of Philosophy David Landy, The Premise That Even Hume Must Accept LANGUAGE AND MIND William G. Lycan, Rosenberg On Proper Names Douglas Long, Why Life is Necessary for Mind: The Significance of Animate Behavior Dorit Bar-On and Mitchell Green, Lionspeak: Communication, Expression, and Meaning David Rosenthal, The Mind and Its (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  37.  60
    Can Sellars’ argument for scientific realism be used against his own scientia mensura principle?Dionysis Christias - 2016 - Synthese 193 (9).
    The purpose of this paper is to evaluate Lange’s argument in support of Sellars’ scientific realism, which, if successful, surprisingly, undermines Sellars’ scientia mensura principle and justifies the anti-Sellarsian view to the effect that certain domains of discourse which use irreducibly normative descriptions and explanations are explanatorily autonomous. It will be argued that Lange’s argument against the layer-cake view is not strictly speaking Sellarsian, since Lange interprets Sellars’ argument in an overly abstract or formal manner. Moreover, I (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38. Proper Names and their Fictional Uses.Heidi Tiedke - 2011 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 89 (4):707 - 726.
    Fictional names present unique challenges for semantic theories of proper names, challenges strong enough to warrant an account of names different from the standard treatment. The theory developed in this paper is motivated by a puzzle that depends on four assumptions: our intuitive assessment of the truth values of certain sentences, the most straightforward treatment of their syntactic structure, semantic compositionality, and metaphysical scruples strong enough to rule out fictional entities, at least. It is shown that (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  39.  77
    Using Proper Names as Intermediaries Between Labelled Entity Representations.Hans Kamp - 2015 - Erkenntnis 80 (2):263-312.
    This paper studies the uses of proper names within a communication-theoretic setting, looking at both the conditions that govern the use of a name by a speaker and those involved in the correct interpretation of the name by her audience. The setting in which these conditions are investigated is provided by an extension of Discourse Representation Theory, MSDRT, in which mental states are represented as combinations of propositional attitudes and entity representations . The first half of the paper (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  40. Sense and No-sense Theories on Proper Names.M. Muqim - 2006 - Indian Philosophical Quarterly 33 (1):93.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41. Proper Names and Relational Modality.Peter Pagin & Kathrin Gluer - 2006 - Linguistics and Philosophy 29 (5):507 - 535.
    Saul Kripke's thesis that ordinary proper names are rigid designators is supported by widely shared intuitions about the occurrence of names in ordinary modal contexts. By those intuitions names are scopeless with respect to the modal expressions. That is, sentences in a pair like (a) Aristotle might have been fond of dogs, (b) Concerning Aristotle, it is true that he might have been fond of dogs will have the same truth value. The same does not in (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  42. Understanding proper names.Michael McKinsey - 2010 - Linguistics and Philosophy 33 (4):325-354.
    There is a fairly general consensus that names are Millian (or Russellian) genuine terms, that is, are singular terms whose sole semantic function is to introduce a referent into the propositions expressed by sentences containing the term. This answers the question as to what sort of proposition is expressed by use of sentences containing names. But there is a second serious semantic problem about proper names, that of how the referents of proper names are (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  43. On the linguistic complexity of proper names.Ora Matushansky - 2008 - Linguistics and Philosophy 31 (5):573-627.
    While proper names in argument positions have received a lot of attention, this cannot be said about proper names in the naming construction, as in “Call me Al”. I argue that in a number of more or less familiar languages the syntax of naming constructions is such that proper names there have to be analyzed as predicates, whose content mentions the name itself (cf. “quotation theories”). If proper names can enter syntax as (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   71 citations  
  44. On predicating proper names.Michael Lockwood - 1975 - Philosophical Review 84 (4):471-498.
  45.  51
    On quasi-names.Alessandro Capone - forthcoming - Ca' Foscari Submission. Translated by Alessandro Capone.
    Abstract -/- In this paper, I shall deal with quasi-(proper) names, that is expressions like ‘Mum’, ‘Dad’, ‘Grandpa’, ‘Grandma’ in English or ‘Papà’, ‘Mamma’, ‘Nonna’, ‘Nonno’ in Italian. I shall use examples both from English and Italian. Quasi-names are directly referential like proper names, even if they apparently exhibit some conceptual materials, which, however, are not active and are inert. They can be used as vocatives or as arguments of verbs. I called terms like ‘Mum’, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. Public Proper Names, Idiolectal Identifying Descriptions.Stavroula Glezakos - 2009 - Linguistics and Philosophy 32 (3):317-326.
    Direct reference theorists tell us that proper names have no semantic value other than their bearers, and that the connection between name and bearer is unmediated by descriptions or descriptive information. And yet, these theorists also acknowledge that we produce our name-containing utterances with descriptions on our minds. After arguing that direct reference proponents have failed to give descriptions their due, I show that appeal to speaker-associated descriptions is required if the direct reference portrayal of speakers wielding and (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  47. Proper names as rigid presuppositions.Emar Maier - 2007 - In Estella Puig-Waldmüller (ed.), Proceedings of Sinn Und Bedeutung 11. pp. 418-32.
    Since Kripke introduced rigid designation as an alternative to the Frege/Russell analysis of referential terms as definite descriptions, there has been an ongoing debate between 'descriptivists' and 'referentialists', mostly focusing on the semantics of proper names. Nowadays descriptivists can draw on a much richer set of linguistic data (including bound and accommodated proper names in discourse) as well as new semantic machinery (E-type syntax/semantics, DRT, presupposition-as-anaphora) to strengthen their case. After reviewing the current state of the (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. On the supposed connection between proper names and singular thought.Rachel Goodman - 2018 - Synthese 195 (1):197-223.
    A thesis I call the name-based singular thought thesis is part of orthodoxy in contemporary philosophy of mind and language: it holds that taking part in communication involving a proper name puts one in a position to entertain singular thoughts about the name’s referent. I argue, first, that proponents of the NBT thesis have failed to explain the phenomenon of name-based singular thoughts, leaving it mysterious how name-use enables singular thoughts. Second, by outlining the reasoning that makes the NBT (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  49.  60
    An Observation on Common Names and Proper Names.John Tienson - 1986 - Analysis 46 (2):73 - 76.
    Common names, for Mill, have both connotation and denotation. Thus ‘horse’ connotes certain properties, and the name ‘horse’ denotes the things that have those properties. By contrast, proper names have no connotations; they do not denote in virtue of the possession of certain properties by their denotations, but so to speak, directly. Thus Socrates received his name by being dubbed ‘Socrates’; and he might just as well have been given any other name. This contrast is misleading. After (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  12
    An observation on common names and proper.John Tienson - 1986 - Analysis 46 (1):73-76.
    Common names, for Mill, have both connotation and denotation. Thus ‘horse’ connotes certain properties, and the name ‘horse’ denotes the things that have those properties. By contrast, proper names have no connotations; they do not denote in virtue of the possession of certain properties by their denotations, but so to speak, directly. Thus Socrates received his name by being dubbed ‘Socrates’; and he might just as well have been given any other name.This contrast is misleading. After all, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 1000